Tuesday, September 3, 2013

Critical Pedagogy and Democratic Education


Critical pedagogies (e.g. Dewey, 1938; Freire, 1993; Shor, 1992; 1996) criticize the imbalance of power between educators and students. Freire (1993) criticizes the “banking” model of education in which the relation between an educator and students is described as a “A over B” relation. In the banking model of education, educators are the primary decision makers and sole deliverers of knowledge. Freire describes the banking approach to teaching and learning as follows:
a) The teacher teaches and the students are taught; b) the teacher knows everything and the students know nothing; c) the teacher thinks and the students are thought about; d) the teacher talks and the students listen-meekly; e) the teacher disciplines and the students are disciplined; f) the teacher chooses and enforces his [her] choice, and the students comply; g) the teacher acts and the students have the illusion of acting through the action of the teacher; h) the teacher chooses the content and the students, who were not consulted, adapt to it. (p. 54)

Freire argues that in the “banking” model of teaching and learning, educators control students’ thinking and action, leading to students’ passivity and inhibiting their “creative power” (p. 58).  For democratic education, Freire (1993) argues, “Education must begin with the solution of the teacher-student contradiction” (p. 72). The contradiction that Freire meant is the hierarchical relationship between the teacher and students in which the teacher is seen the expert who owns the knowledge and knows everything and students know nothing. Rather, Freire emphasizes the partnership between the educator and students. He describes such partnership as one in which both students and the educator learn from each other in a way that “they become jointly responsible for a process in which all grow” (p. 61). To accomplish such partnership, there should be a horizontal relationship between the educator and students in which the role of the educator is “to create, together with students” the conditions of learning (p. 62). Freire argues that dialogue has the power to break the vertical relationship between teachers and students and transform it to a democratic relation in which both teachers and students have a voice. He emphasizes, “Through dialogue, the teacher-of-the-students and the students-of the-teacher […] The teacher is no longer merely the one who teaches, but one who is himself taught in dialogue with the students, who in their turn while being taught also teach” (p. 61).
Much in line with Freire’s ideas, the critical educator Ira Shor (1992; 1996) asserts that students’ meaningful participation in their learning provides an important basis for constructing the fundamental imperatives of a strong democracy. Shor (1992) argues that democracy is a process of open communication and mutual governance in a community of shared power, where all members can express ideas, frame purposes, and act on intentions. Shor (1996) further argues that democratic principles can be fostered and realized in the classroom community when power in the classroom is shared so that students are able to actively participate in the learning process. For Shor, without student active participation in decision-making, the classroom will be a place of undemocratic transfers of information, and students will develop as authority-dependent subordinates, not as democratic citizens. In contrast, Shor explains, when higher education seeks to maximize students’ participation in decision-making, they develop intellectual curiosity, scientific thinking, cooperative relations, social habits, and self-discipline. Sharing the decision-making power with students can serve as an important means to help realize the vital goals of democratic education. 

However, teaching democratically by involving students in the decision making power does not mean that faculty abdicate their authority (Schultz & Oyler, 2006; Weimer, 2002; Oyler, 1996; Brookfield, 1995). Kreisberg (1992) agues, “‘Power with’ is not a zero-sum proposition where one person gains the capacity to achieve his or her desires at the expense of others” (p. 71). Rather, the “power with” relation, Kreisberg explains, manifests in relationships of “co-agency”, in which “individuals and groups fulfill their desires by acting together” (pp. 85-86). Therefore, as Oyler (1996) argues, sharing power with students does not mean that the instructor “moves out of the students’ way to the soft place of abdicated authority” (p. 24). Rather, Schultz and Oyler (2006) explain, the instructor should remain a member of the classroom as decisions are being made. Also, Shor (1992) argues that sharing power with students does not mean students can do whatever they like in the classroom, neither can the teacher do whatever she or he likes. What it does mean, as Brookfield (1995) explains, is that educators make an effort to create conditions under which all voices can be heard, and in which educational processes are seen to be open and genuine negotiation. 

No comments:

Post a Comment